What is 0^0?

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

When calculus books state that 00 is an indeterminate form, they mean that there are functions f(x) and g(x) such that f(x) approaches 0 and g(x) approaches 0 as x approaches 0, and that one must evaluate the limit of [f(x)]g(x) as x approaches 0. But what if 0 is just a number? Then, we argue, the value is perfectly well-defined, contrary to what many texts say. In fact, 00 = 1!

What is 0^0? - Introduction

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

When calculus books state that 00 is an indeterminate form, they mean that there are functions f(x) and g(x) such that f(x) approaches 0 and g(x) approaches 0 as x approaches 0, and that one must evaluate the limit of [f(x)]g(x) as x approaches 0. But what if 0 is just a number? Then, we argue, the value is perfectly well-defined, contrary to what many texts say. In fact, 00 = 1!

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.

What is 0^0? - Today's Algebra Books

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

Pick up a high school mathematics textbook today and you will see that 00 is treated as an indeterminate form. For example, the following is taken from a current New York Regents text [6]:

We recall the rule for dividing powers with like bases:

xa/xb = xa-b (x not equal to 0) (1)

If we do not require a > b, then a may be equal to b. When a = b:

xa/xb = xa/xa = xa-a = x0

(2)

but

xa / xa = 1 (3)

Therefore, in order for x0 to be meaningful, we must make the following definition:

x0 = 1 (x not equal to 0) (4)
Since the definition x0 = 1 is based upon division, and division by 0 is not possible, we have stated that x is not equal to 0. Actually, the expression 00 (0 to the zero power) is one of several indeterminate expressions in mathematics. It is not possible to assign a value to an indeterminate expression.

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.

What is 0^0? - Indeterminate Forms

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

Calculus textbooks also discuss the problem, usually in a section dealing with L'Hospital's Rule. Suppose we are given two functions, f(x) and g(x), with the properties that \(\lim_{x\rightarrow a} f(x)=0\) and \(\lim_{x\rightarrow a} g(x)=0.\) When attempting to evaluate [f(x)]g(x) in the limit as x approaches a, we are told rightly that this is an indeterminate form of type 00 and that the limit can have various values of f and g. This begs the question: are these the same? Can we distinguish 00 as an indeterminate form and 00 as a number?

The treatment of 00 has been discussed for several hundred years. Donald Knuth [7] points out that an Italian count by the name of Guglielmo Libri published several papers in the 1830s on the subject of 00 and its properties. However, in his Elements of Algebra, (1770) [4], which was published years before Libri, Euler wrote,

As in this series of powers each term is found by multiplying the preceding term by a, which increases the exponent by 1; so when any term is given, we may also find the preceding term, if we divide by a, because this diminishes the exponent by 1. This shews that the term which precedes the first term a1 must necessarily be a/a or 1; and, if we proceed according to the exponents, we immediately conclude, that the term which precedes the first must be a0; and hence we deduce this remarkable property, that a0 is always equal to 1, however great or small the value of the number a may be, and even when a is nothing; that is to say, a0 is equal to 1.

More from Euler: In his Introduction to Analysis of the Infinite (1748) [5], he writes :

Let the exponential to be considered be az where a is a constant and the exponent z is a variable .... If z = 0, then we have a0 = 1. If a = 0, we take a huge jump in the values of az. As long as the value of z remains positive, or greater than zero, then we always have az = 0. If z = 0, then a0 = 1.

Euler defines the logarithm of y as the value of the function z, such that az = y. He writes that it is understood that the base a of the logarithm should be a number greater than 1, thus avoiding his earlier reference to a possible problem with 00.

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.

What is 0^0? - George Baron

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

Defining powers is often carelessly done. Almost thirty years before Libri's first paper, George Baron published "A short Disquisition, concerning the Definition, of the word Power, in Arithmetic and Algebra" in The Mathematical Correspondent (1804). In this paper [1], Baron begins the discussion with the following definition:

The powers of any number, are the successive products, arising from unity, continually multiplied, by that number.

As an example, he writes that 1 × 5 = 5, which is the first power of 5, and 1 × 5 × 5 = 25, which is the second power of 5, etc. The first, second, etc., powers are then conveniently expressed as 51, 52, etc. In the same manner, the powers of any number x might be represented as x1, x2, etc., in which x1 = 1 × x, x2 = x1 × x, etc. After stating a few corollaries, Baron writes:

Let us, therefore, next inquire, whether the same definition, will not lead us to a clear and intelligible solution, of the mysterious paradoxes, resulting from the common definition, when applied, to what is denominated, the nothingth power of numbers.

Baron then addresses the rules for dividing powers (look back to the argument from the high school text), but he develops a different conclusion:

If the multiplication by x, be abstracted from the first power of x, by means of division; the power will become nothing but the unit will remain: for \(\frac{x^1}{x} = \frac{1\times x}{x} =1,\) and hence it is plain that x0 = 1, when x represents any number whatever. But since the number x, is here unlimited with regard to greatness, it follows, that, the nothingth power of an infinite number is equal to a unit.

Baron gives credit to both William Emerson (1780) [3] and Jared Mansfield (1802) [9] who wrote on the subject of "nothing." Baron takes their arguments one step further and postulates that the number x can be any number, great or small:

To pursue the application of our definition, to quantity in the ultimate extremity of smallness, let us suppose x to represent any fractional quantity; or in other words, let x denote any magnitude, expressed in numbers, by means of some part of its measuring unit: then by the definition x1 = 1 × x. Let now this multiplication by x, be abstracted; and for the reasons heretofore advanced, we have x0 = 1. Now since x here represents a fractional quantity, independent of any limitation, in respect to smallness; we may therefore suppose x, by means of continual diminution, or decrease, to pass from its present value, through every degree of smallness, until it become nothing; then it will be evident, that, during this diminution or decrease of x, x0 will continue equal to an invariable unit; and that precisely at the instant, when x becomes nothing, x0, or 00 = 1.

Baron never mentions the term indeterminate form, and he in fact ends his treatise with the following:

Also, since x0 = 1, whatever be the value of x; of consequence; in every system of logarithms, the logarithm of 1 = 0.

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.

What is 0^0? - Guglielmo Libri and Augustin Cauchy

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

According to Knuth, Libri's 1833 paper [8] "did produce several ripples in mathematical waters when it originally appeared, because it stirred up a controversy about whether 00 is defined." Most mathematicians at the time agreed that 00 = 1, even though Augustin-Louis Cauchy had listed 00 in a table of undefined forms in his book entitled Cours D'Analyse (1821) [2]. Evidently, Libri's argument was not convincing, so August Möbius came to his defense. Möbius tried to defend Libri by presenting a supposed proof of 00 = 1 (in essence, a proof that \(\lim_{x\rightarrow {0^+}} x^x=1\)). After confrontations from another mathematician resulted, the paper "was quietly omitted from the historical record when the collected works of Möbius were ultimately published." Knuth goes on to write that the debate ended with the result that 00 should be undefined, and then he states,

 

"No, no, ten thousand times no!"

Perhaps Cauchy was developing the notion of 00 as an undefined limiting form. Then the limiting value of [f(x)]g(x) is not known a priori when each of f(x) and g(x) approach 0 independently. According to Knuth, "the value of 00 is less defined than, say, the value of 0 + 0." He reminds us to recall the binomial theorem:

\[(x + y)^n = \sum_{k=0}^n {n \choose k} x^k y^{n-k}.\]

If this theorem is to hold for at least one nonnegative integer, then mathematicians "must believe that 00 = 1," for we can plug in x = 0 and y = 1 to get 1 on the left and 00 on the right.

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.

What is 0^0? - Examples

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

In 1970, Herbert Vaughan [10] argued for the explicit recognition of evaluating 00 = 1. He aimed to show "that there is a good deal of motivation for defining '00' to be a numeral for 1." He provided three examples.

Example 1. Vaughan gave the infinite geometric progression

 
\[\sum_{n=1}^{\infty} x^{n-1} = \frac{1}{1-x} \mbox{ for } | x | < 1.\]
(6)

If \(x = 0,\) then \(\vert x\vert = \vert 0\vert < 1,\) which leads to

 
\[\sum_{n=1}^{\infty} 0^{n-1} = \frac{1}{1-0} = 1.\]
(7)

The infinite sum can be expanded as 00 + 01 + 02 + … = 1. As stated by Vaughan, if 00 is not defined, this summation is senseless. Further, if 00 ≠ 1, then the summation is false.

Example 2. This example arises from the infinite summation for ex, which can be written as

 
\[\sum_{n=1}^{\infty} \frac{x^{n-1}}{(n-1)!} = e^x \mbox{, for all } x.\]
(8)

Everyone agrees that 0! = 1, so in the case where x = 0, the sum becomes

 
\[\sum_{n=1}^{\infty} \frac{0^{n-1}}{(n-1)!} = e^0 = 1.\]
(9)

The sum can be expanded as

 
\[\frac{0^0}{0!} + \frac{0^1}{1!} + \frac{0^2}{2!} + \cdots = \frac{0^0}{1} + 0 + 0 + \cdots = 0^0.\]
(10

The right-hand-side of the summation is e0 = 1, so 00 = 1.

Example 3. A third example given by Vaughan involves the cardinal number of a set of mappings. In set theory, exponentiation of a cardinal number is defined as follows:

ab is the cardinal number of the set of mappings of a set with b members into a set with a members.

For instance, 23 = 8 because there are eight ways to map the set { x, y, z } into the set { a, b }. In order to calculate 00, determine the number of mappings of the empty set into itself. There is precisely one such mapping, which is itself the set of the empty set. "So, as far as cardinal numbers are concerned," wrote Vaughan, "00 = 1."

When might a mathematician want 00 to be something that is not indeterminate? If, for example, we are discussing the function f(x, y) = xy, the origin is a discontinuity of the function. No matter what value may be assigned to 00, the function xy can never be continuous at x = y = 0. Why not? The limit of xy along the line x = 0 is 0, but the limit along the line y = 0 is 1, not 0. For consistency and usefulness, a "natural" choice would be to define 00 = 1.

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.

What is 0^0? - Conclusion and Bibliography

Author(s): 
Michael Huber and V. Frederick Rickey

 

In keeping with the honored pedagogical technique of "First tell 'em what you are going to tell 'em, then tell 'em, then tell 'em what you told 'em," we summarize. If you are dealing with limits, then 00 is an indeterminate form, but if you are dealing with ordinary algebra, then 00 = 1.

 

 

Bibliography

 
  1. George Baron, "A short Disquisition, concerning the Definition, of the word Power, in Arithmetic and Algebra," The Mathematical Correspondent (1804), pages 59 - 66. Available here (pdf download) and from Google Books beginning here.
     
  2. Augustin-Louis Cauchy, Cours d'Analyse de l'Ecole Royale Polytechnique (1821). In his Oeuvres Complètes, series 2, volume 3, available here from Gallica Digital Library.
     
  3. William Emerson, A treatise of algebra, in two books, 2nd edition, J. Nourse, London, 1780. Title page and pages 208-213, including the problem "To explain the several properties of (0) nothing, and infinity," available here (pdf download), courtesy of United States Military Academy Library.
     
  4. Leonhard Euler, Elements of Algebra, translated by Rev. John Hewlett, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1984, pages 50 - 51.
     
  5. Leonhard Euler, Introduction to Analysis of the Infinite, translated by John D. Blanton, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1988, pages 75 - 76.
     
  6. E. Keenan, A. X. Gantert, and I. Dressler, Mathematics B, Amsco School Publications, Inc., New York, 2002.
     
  7. Donald Knuth, "Two Notes on Notation," The American Mathematical Monthly, Volume 99, Number 5, May 1992, pages 403 - 422. This is available in JSTOR.
     
  8. Guillaume Libri, "Mèmoire sur les functions discontinues," Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 10 (1833), pages 303 - 316. Available here (pdf download), courtesy of Göttingen State and University Library Digitalization Center (GDZ).
     
  9. Jared Mansfield, Essays, mathematical and physical: containing new theories and illustrations of some very important and difficult subjects of the sciences, W. W. Morse, New Haven, 1802. Title page and pages 12-17, including first five pages of the essay "Of Nothing and Infinity," available here (pdf download), courtesy of United States Military Academy Library.
     
  10. Herbert E. Vaughan, "The Expression of 00," The Mathematics Teacher, Volume 63, February 1970, page 111.

 

Editor's note: This article was published in March of 2008.